Michael,
I think I, too, am a fan of abduction, even though I am not so sure I know what it is. To me it means the use of metaphors to explain. A great many years ago, when I was still in the monkey business, I was able to demonstrate that the "social structure" of a monkey "group" was the same, whether one convened it as a whole or only as a series of n(n-1)/2 pairs of monkeys, suggesting that a monkey social group is an aggregate property of the behavior of its pairs. It was a startling observation, one I did not expect and one I did not altogether trust. What it suggested is that a group of monkeys, maintained in individual cages, and paired for observation, and who never had physical contact with monkeys outside of those meetings, was a good metaphor (model) for the group operating as a group in the ordinary sense. This is an example of a very low level abduction. Natural selection theory ... the idea that what happens in a breeders barnyard or stable etc. can be taken as a model for what happens in nature ... is an example of a very high level abduction. Evolution ... the idea that the change in species through time is akin to the ramification of a trees branches at it grows upward to the light .... is another. Good metaphors stimulate thought and experiment, but a metaphor maker has a deep responsibility to stipulate which parts of his metaphor are facetious ... designed for fun and cognitive promotion, not part of what Mary Brenda Hesse calls "the positive heuristic of the metaphor". Famous authors of widely read books often get away with ignoring that responsibility, viz, Richard Dawkins and his Selfish Gene. So. Are we talking about the same thing when we talk about abduction? As a man with a stiff hip, abduction is a concept I can use some help with. Nick ----- Original Message ----- From: Michael Agar To: nickthompson at earthlink.net Cc: friam at redfish.com Sent: 8/14/2006 1:00:53 PM Subject: Popper misuse Hi Nick. I'm actually an abduction fan myself. I shouldn't have taken Popper's name in vain, since all I really meant was falsification. Validity comes out of the research that precedes a model, the model explores and clarifies a core argument of that research, then in science the argument is put to the test in any number of imaginative ways where procedures are explicit and capable of falsifying or at least complicating the argument. Not everyone's cup of code by a long shot, but one I find useful. I don't think very many people think this way either (: Mike On Aug 14, 2006, at 10:36 AM, Nicholas Thompson wrote: Mike A. writes: How do we make clear the core of a problem through constructing an illustration of our own beliefs and assumptions and say that's exactly what both great science and great art do. Science then has the obligation to challenge it against new instances of the problem in the classic Popperian way. One trouble with Popper is, of course, that people just dont think that way. We engage in induction no matter how illogical it may be. Somebody I knew had a small animal skin.... ferret or something ... nailed to a board at one end. When you petted it, it arched its back, so to speak. Should we conclude that that is why cats arch their backs when you pet them???? Probably not. The other trouble with Popper is, as David Stove pointed out, that EVERY DEDUCTIVE INFERENCE REQUIRES INDUCTION TO GET IT INTO THE REALM OF PRACTICAL EXPERIMENT. So, for instance, as we are busily nailing our live cat to a board to test our deductive inference, we must assume that all our operations have the same effects in the live cat and in the ferret skin case, and this assumption is an INDUCTIVE STEP subject to all of Popper's doubts about the possibility of induction. I think Stove concluded that we just had to suck it up and go back to making rules for inductive inference, dubious as the whole enterprise is. So then the question would be, under what conditions do we accept that when the simple agents that we send forth to do battle in our models product the same collective behavior as the apparently real agents we see around us, that the real agents actually behave by the same underlying rules as the our created ones? Stove wrote a subsequent book on induction, but I havent read it. Has anybody??? [Original Message] From: <[hidden email]> To: <friam at redfish.com> Date: 8/14/2006 12:00:21 PM Subject: Friam Digest, Vol 38, Issue 29 Send Friam mailing list submissions to friam at redfish.com To subscribe or unsubscribe via the World Wide Web, visit http://redfish.com/mailman/listinfo/friam_redfish.com or, via email, send a message with subject or body 'help' to friam-request at redfish.com You can reach the person managing the list at friam-owner at redfish.com When replying, please edit your Subject line so it is more specific than "Re: Contents of Friam digest..." Today's Topics: 1. the odd question (Phil Henshaw) (Nicholas Thompson) 2. The art of agent-based modeling (Jochen Fromm) 3. Re: The art of agent-based modeling (Marcus G. Daniels) 4. Re: The art of agent-based modeling (Jochen Fromm) 5. Re: The art of agent-based modeling (mgd at santafe.edu) 6. Re: The art of agent-based modeling (Michael Agar) ---------------------------------------------------------------------- Message: 1 Date: Sun, 13 Aug 2006 23:40:29 -0400 From: "Nicholas Thompson" <[hidden email]> Subject: [FRIAM] the odd question (Phil Henshaw) To: "Friam" <Friam at redfish.com> Message-ID: <380-22006811434029151 at earthlink.net> Content-Type: text/plain; charset="us-ascii" Phil, I hate it when one of my topics gets dropped, and therefore feel guilty for being one of the DROPPERS, here. Sometimes the discussions get so far reaching and technical that I am forced to "pass over them in silence" as Wittegenstein said. the only piece of your message that I have anything nearly competent to say about is your .... "when modern science took an interest in complex systems it, concentrated on theory rather than on carefully documenting the physical phenomenon." I wonder if this isnt a common occcurence in science. Think of Evolutionary Biology Darwinism has a much stronger hand on its theories than it does on the things those theories explain. Think for a moment about our realtive grasp on "natural selection" and "adaptation". Natural selection is supposed to the be "cause" of adaptation, yet we seem to understand the cause much better than we understand the effect. Ask an evolutionary biologist to define adaptation: 90 percent will use the word natural selection in their definitions, because they dont have clue what they mean by adaptation. Thus, it doesnt surprise me that wise and sophisticated people can talk about the theory of complexity without having a clue what they mean by it. I got a group of people to gether at Clark a few years back to start a research project on emergence in human social groups. We were NEVER able to come up with a phenomenon that everybody agreed was an instance of emergence. -------------- next part -------------- An HTML attachment was scrubbed... URL: /pipermail/friam_redfish.com/attachments/20060813/be24b22f/attachment-0001.h tml ------------------------------ Message: 2 Date: Mon, 14 Aug 2006 14:14:55 +0200 From: "Jochen Fromm" <[hidden email]> Subject: [FRIAM] The art of agent-based modeling To: "'The Friday Morning Applied Complexity Coffee Group'" <friam at redfish.com> Message-ID: <000701c6bf9b$41129210$976fa8c0 at Toshiba> Content-Type: text/plain; charset="US-ASCII" One question I meet again and again if I try to make meaningful agent-based simulations is: - How do we simulate the core of a problem without merely constructing an illustration of our own beliefs and assumptions ? In other words: How detailed should an agent-based simulation be ? If the goal is "to capture the principal laws behind the exciting variety of new phenomena that become apparent when the many units of a complex system interact", as Tamas Vicsek says in http://angel.eltehu/~vicsek/images/complex.pdf then how do we design models that are complex enough but not too complex ? -If the simulation is too simple and matches your own theoretical ideas, then no matter how good these ideas are it is always easy to criticize that the simulation is either not realistic enough or only constructed to illustrate your own ideas and assumptions. -If the simulation is too complex and matches official experimental data, everything takes a lot amount of time (creation, setup and execution of the experiment and finally the cumbersome analysis of the complex outcomes), and it becomes increasingly difficult to identify the principal laws, because it is easy to get lost in the data or bogged down in details The "art of agent-based modeling" looks really like an art to me, something only mastered by a few scientists (for instance Axelrod). Grimm et al. propose 'pattern-oriented modeling', Macy and Willer say "Keep it simple" and "Test validity". What do you think is the best solution for this problem ? Macy and Willer "From Factors to Actors: Computational Sociology and Agent-Based Modeling" http://www.casos.cs.cmu.edu/education/phd/classpapers/Macy_Factors_2001.pdf Grimm et al. "Pattern-oriented modeling of agent-based complex systems" Science Vol. 310. no. 5750 (2005) 987-991 http://www.ufz.de/index.php?de=4976 -J. -----Original Message----- From: Michael Agar Sent: Saturday, August 12, 2006 5:05 PM To: The Friday Morning Applied Complexity Coffee Group Subject: [FRIAM] complexity and society [...] If you are considering a model, I like Axelrod's way of thinking about them. He sees them as "thought experiment labs" for a conclusion based on social research. So first of all the social research has to be solid to really do it properly. More often than not it isn't. The lab let's you test arguments of the form, if people do things in particular ways properties will emerge at the level of society. By "test" I mean it lets you see if the conclusion can be "generated," to use Epstein and Axtell's concept, in just the way your social research suggests that it can. It's a way of making the argument that underlies the conclusion explicit so it can be better evaluated, and it allows for exploration of the space of results that the same argument produces and alternative spaces given control parameter changes. It's a test of plausibility and an exercise in clarity, nothing more, nothing less. [...] ------------------------------ Message: 3 Date: Mon, 14 Aug 2006 08:07:05 -0600 From: "Marcus G. Daniels" <[hidden email]> Subject: Re: [FRIAM] The art of agent-based modeling To: The Friday Morning Applied Complexity Coffee Group <friam at redfish.com> Message-ID: <44E08389.5070109 at santafe.edu> Content-Type: text/plain; charset=ISO-8859-1; format=flowed Jochen, -If the simulation is too complex and matches official experimental data, everything takes a lot amount of time (creation, setup and execution of the experiment and finally the cumbersome analysis of the complex outcomes), and it becomes increasingly difficult to identify the principal laws, because it is easy to get lost in the data or bogged down in details This may be a false choice. In the case of having some data of moderate resolution, there's no point in making a hugely elaborate model and simulation, because you'll never be able to validate beyond your data anyway. And if you don't validate, although the modeling still may be useful as an thought experiment, it isn't science. You have to be able to say something that can be shown to be wrong. If you do aim to learn things about the world and then predict them it's not desirable to have giant black box with lots of moving parts. It's better, if at all possible, to have a simple story and make the simulation nothing more than apparatus to help extend the data so that the dynamics can be studied by theoreticians. Another mode of use for ABMs is to lower expectations of theoretical traction and opportunistically look for ways a model makes useful predictions and then modify the model in that direction over time. This is a risky and expensive craft, but one that might have high enough payoffs to consider (e.g. national security). It depends on the data and what is of interest. If the data tells you about a number of rare events, and it is these events is what you really care about, then it may make sense to loosely model everyday behaviors and focus on model microstructure that can create the rare events you care about. Finally, sometimes microstructure is known with clearly defined degrees of freedom, and the dynamics are of interest. Consider modeling a factory where different assembly regimes are to be evaluated.. There's no need to validate here because the whole exercise is to answer what-ifs about realizable specific systems. Marcus ------------------------------ Message: 4 Date: Mon, 14 Aug 2006 17:04:40 +0200 From: "Jochen Fromm" <[hidden email]> Subject: Re: [FRIAM] The art of agent-based modeling To: "'The Friday Morning Applied Complexity Coffee Group'" <friam at redfish.com> Message-ID: <000801c6bfb2$f76ede80$976fa8c0 at Toshiba> Content-Type: text/plain; charset="US-ASCII" Of course it is the essence of science to verify hypotheses by experiments. Yet sometimes we have neither suitable experimental data nor a solid theory, for example in the case of very large agent-based systems (for instance for the self-organization and self-management of large internet applications on planetary scale, or the modeling of historical processes with millions of actors). It is hardly possible to examine these systems without simplified models, and in this case the questions I mentioned seem to be justified. In traditional "factor-based" or "equation-based modeling" we use differential equations and everything is based on a soild theory: mathematics. This traditional modeling has a century-long history and we know the suitable parameters, equations and models. Agent-based modeling has a short history, we don't know exactly the suitable parameters, agents and models, and worst of all it is not based on a solid theoretical theorem-lemma-proof science or calculus like mathematics. What is missing is a solid science of ABM or a new science of complexity - something in the direction of Wolfram's NKS idea (exploring computational universes in a systematic way). Just as formal, symmetrical and regular systems can be described by mathematics and 'equation-based modeling', complex systems can in principle be described by a 'NKS' and agent-based modeling - which seems to be more an art than a science. -J. ------------------------------ Message: 5 Date: Mon, 14 Aug 2006 09:50:59 -0600 From: [hidden email] Subject: Re: [FRIAM] The art of agent-based modeling To: The Friday Morning Applied Complexity Coffee Group <friam at redfish.com> Message-ID: <1155570659.44e09be35f52a at webmail.santafe.edu> Content-Type: text/plain; charset=ISO-8859-1 Quoting Jochen Fromm <fromm at vs.uni-kassel.de>: Just as formal, symmetrical and regular systems can be described by mathematics and 'equation-based modeling', complex systems can in principle be described by a 'NKS' and agent-based modeling - which seems to be more an art than a science. In context, I think is a verification issue. ABMs are useful for poking around a complicated system to see what matters and what doesn't by using a familiar and direct way of describing things, and to leave the abstractions for later. ABMs complement traditional techniques of analysis by extending data. The imperative programming languages that are typically used to make the simulations are prone to a variety of programming mistakes but the continue to be used because 1) they are common and 2) they provide an easy way to think about side effects (e.g. modifications to a landscape). Equation-based modelling is more like functional programming, e.g. programming languages like Haskell that are side-effect free. I see ABMs moving to these kinds of programming languages so that components of a simulation can be shown to be correct, and preferably by automated means. As a practical matter, I think it isn't a big deal. Unit testing during development by experienced programmers/modelers does a good job of shaking out bugs. Marcus ------------------------------ Message: 6 Date: Mon, 14 Aug 2006 09:58:05 -0600 From: Michael Agar <[hidden email]> Subject: Re: [FRIAM] The art of agent-based modeling To: The Friday Morning Applied Complexity Coffee Group <friam at redfish.com> Message-ID: <18528635-4305-4EB8-8D01-CA9C885E3826 at anth.umd.edu> Content-Type: text/plain; charset=US-ASCII; delsp=yes; format=flowed On Aug 14, 2006, at 6:14 AM, Jochen Fromm wrote: - How do we simulate the core of a problem without merely constructing an illustration of our own beliefs and assumptions ? I'd change this to How do we make clear the core of a problem through constructing an illustration of our own beliefs and assumptions and say that's exactly what both great science and great art do. Science then has the obligation to challenge it against new instances of the problem in the classic Popperian way. Mike ------------------------------ _______________________________________________ Friam mailing list Friam at redfish.com http://redfish.com/mailman/listinfo/friam_redfish.com End of Friam Digest, Vol 38, Issue 29 ************************************* -------------- next part -------------- An HTML attachment was scrubbed... URL: /pipermail/friam_redfish.com/attachments/20060814/b0d72025/attachment-0001.html |
Nick--Here's a blurb on abduction, part of a lecture I did earlier
this year on how to tell if something is a "real" ethnography. The full pack of lies available on request. The delete key might be a better choice. Mike Peirce?s abductive logic formalizes this critical part of any ethnographic trajectory. Let me borrow from an unpublished paper by Michael Hoffman, an artificial intelligence researcher at Bielefeld University. Here, in Peirce?s own words, as quoted by Hoffman, is abductive logic: The surprising fact, F, is observed If H were true, F would be a matter of course Hence, there is reason to suspect that H is true The ?surprising fact F? echoes what I call ?rich points.? Rich points are the raw material of ethnographic research. They run the gamut from incomprehensible surprise to departure from expectations to glitches in an aggregate data set. As Peirce would have advocated, the purpose of ethnography is to go forth into the world, find and experience rich points, and then take them seriously as a signal of a difference between what you know and what you need to learn to understand and explain what just happened. People are said to be creatures of habit and seekers of certainty. Abduction turns them into the opposite. How do we make sense of all these big and little ?F?s?? We don?t just box them in with old concepts in the style of inductive logic. Instead, we imagine ?H?s? that might explain them. We imagine. The surprise F, the rich point, calls on us to create, to think, to make up an antecedent H that does indeed imply the consequent. Where did that F come from? Well, what if? H? Rather than reaching into the box and pulling out a concept ready at hand, we make up some new ones. Any trajectory in the ethnographic space will run on the fuel of abduction. You?ll read or see how surprises came up, how they were taken seriously, and how they were explained using concepts not anticipated when the story started. We need to reign in our enthusiasm a bit. Peirce wants some plausibility. Stephen King just wrote a new thriller where, the review said, a pulse transmitted through cell phones turns users who happen to be calling at the time into monsters. The plot appeals to me, but the likelihood that the story will turn into an actual news item is pretty slim. It?s probably an entertaining read, but a plausible scenario? Peirce also wants us to follow up the abductive epiphany with some tedious work. And the tedious work looks a lot like old-fashioned science. We need to systematically collect, compare and contrast, try to prove the new H ? P link wrong, all that systematic drudgery, whether we?re in the lab or in the field. It reminds me of one of my favorite Einstein quotes, that he never made a significant scientific discovery using rational analytic thought. But he did a lot of work after the discovery to test it out. And it reminds me of Edison?s famous quote, since I mentioned his museum a while back--Genius is 1% inspiration and 99% perspiration. And it reminds me of why I like the first days of ethnographic work the best, because they are the most creative part where the learning curve accelerates exponentially. Hoffman also emphasizes that the range of imagination in play is bounded by history. We can only stretch so far is the sad moral of the story. Vygotsky?s ?zone of proximal development,? about which I learned much from education colleagues during my visit, is a case in point. But still, some stretching is better than no stretching at all. That?s the message that abduction conveys. On Aug 14, 2006, at 2:37 PM, Nicholas Thompson wrote: > Michael, > > I think I, too, am a fan of abduction, even though I am not so sure > I know what it is. To me it means the use of metaphors to > explain. A great many years ago, when I was still in the monkey > business, I was able to demonstrate that the "social structure" of > a monkey "group" was the same, whether one convened it as a whole > or only as a series of n(n-1)/2 pairs of monkeys, suggesting that a > monkey social group is an aggregate property of the behavior of its > pairs. It was a startling observation, one I did not expect and > one I did not altogether trust. What it suggested is that a group > of monkeys, maintained in individual cages, and paired for > observation, and who never had physical contact with monkeys > outside of those meetings, was a good metaphor (model) for the > group operating as a group in the ordinary sense. > > This is an example of a very low level abduction. Natural > selection theory ... the idea that what happens in a breeders > barnyard or stable etc. can be taken as a model for what happens in > nature ... is an example of a very high level abduction. > Evolution ... the idea that the change in species through time is > akin to the ramification of a trees branches at it grows upward to > the light .... is another. Good metaphors stimulate thought and > experiment, but a metaphor maker has a deep responsibility to > stipulate which parts of his metaphor are facetious ... designed > for fun and cognitive promotion, not part of what Mary Brenda Hesse > calls "the positive heuristic of the metaphor". Famous authors of > widely read books often get away with ignoring that responsibility, > viz, Richard Dawkins and his Selfish Gene. > > So. Are we talking about the same thing when we talk about > abduction? As a man with a stiff hip, abduction is a concept I can > use some help with. > > Nick > age] -------------- next part -------------- An HTML attachment was scrubbed... URL: /pipermail/friam_redfish.com/attachments/20060814/f3ed945c/attachment.html |
In reply to this post by Nick Thompson
I puzzled about why someone would muck up a perfectly good English word
with an entirely foreign meaning, but the philosophical use is well described on http://www.philosophypages.com/dy/a.htm#abd , something about using heuristics http://www.philosophypages.com/dy/h2.htm#heur whatever they are. It almost seems to describe the form of reasoning that careful human thinkers probably used for most of the past million years or so, and would probably still have a use for confusing problems. Phil Henshaw ????.?? ? `?.???? ~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~ 680 Ft. Washington Ave NY NY 10040 tel: 212-795-4844 e-mail: pfh at synapse9.com explorations: www.synapse9.com <http://www.synapse9.com/> -----Original Message----- From: [hidden email] [mailto:[hidden email]] On Behalf Of Nicholas Thompson Sent: Monday, August 14, 2006 4:37 PM To: Michael Agar Cc: Friam Subject: Re: [FRIAM] Agar, Abduction Michael, I think I, too, am a fan of abduction, even though I am not so sure I know what it is. To me it means the use of metaphors to explain. A great many years ago, when I was still in the monkey business, I was able to demonstrate that the "social structure" of a monkey "group" was the same, whether one convened it as a whole or only as a series of n(n-1)/2 pairs of monkeys, suggesting that a monkey social group is an aggregate property of the behavior of its pairs. It was a startling observation, one I did not expect and one I did not altogether trust. What it suggested is that a group of monkeys, maintained in individual cages, and paired for observation, and who never had physical contact with monkeys outside of those meetings, was a good metaphor (model) for the group operating as a group in the ordinary sense. This is an example of a very low level abduction. Natural selection theory ... the idea that what happens in a breeders barnyard or stable etc. can be taken as a model for what happens in nature ... is an example of a very high level abduction. Evolution ... the idea that the change in species through time is akin to the ramification of a trees branches at it grows upward to the light .... is another. Good metaphors stimulate thought and experiment, but a metaphor maker has a deep responsibility to stipulate which parts of his metaphor are facetious ... designed for fun and cognitive promotion, not part of what Mary Brenda Hesse calls "the positive heuristic of the metaphor". Famous authors of widely read books often get away with ignoring that responsibility, viz, Richard Dawkins and his Selfish Gene. So. Are we talking about the same thing when we talk about abduction? As a man with a stiff hip, abduction is a concept I can use some help with. Nick ----- Original Message ----- From: Michael <mailto:[hidden email]> Agar To: nickthompson at earthlink.net Cc: friam at redfish.com Sent: 8/14/2006 1:00:53 PM Subject: Popper misuse Hi Nick. I'm actually an abduction fan myself. I shouldn't have taken Popper's name in vain, since all I really meant was falsification. Validity comes out of the research that precedes a model, the model explores and clarifies a core argument of that research, then in science the argument is put to the test in any number of imaginative ways where procedures are explicit and capable of falsifying or at least complicating the argument. Not everyone's cup of code by a long shot, but one I find useful. I don't think very many people think this way either (: Mike On Aug 14, 2006, at 10:36 AM, Nicholas Thompson wrote: Mike A. writes: How do we make clear the core of a problem through constructing an illustration of our own beliefs and assumptions and say that's exactly what both great science and great art do. Science then has the obligation to challenge it against new instances of the problem in the classic Popperian way. One trouble with Popper is, of course, that people just dont think that way. We engage in induction no matter how illogical it may be. Somebody I knew had a small animal skin.... ferret or something ... nailed to a board at one end. When you petted it, it arched its back, so to speak. Should we conclude that that is why cats arch their backs when you pet them???? Probably not. The other trouble with Popper is, as David Stove pointed out, that EVERY DEDUCTIVE INFERENCE REQUIRES INDUCTION TO GET IT INTO THE REALM OF PRACTICAL EXPERIMENT. So, for instance, as we are busily nailing our live cat to a board to test our deductive inference, we must assume that all our operations have the same effects in the live cat and in the ferret skin case, and this assumption is an INDUCTIVE STEP subject to all of Popper's doubts about the possibility of induction. I think Stove concluded that we just had to suck it up and go back to making rules for inductive inference, dubious as the whole enterprise is. So then the question would be, under what conditions do we accept that when the simple agents that we send forth to do battle in our models product the same collective behavior as the apparently real agents we see around us, that the real agents actually behave by the same underlying rules as the our created ones? Stove wrote a subsequent book on induction, but I havent read it. Has anybody??? [Original Message] From: <[hidden email]> To: <friam at redfish.com> Date: 8/14/2006 12:00:21 PM Subject: Friam Digest, Vol 38, Issue 29 Send Friam mailing list submissions to friam at redfish.com To subscribe or unsubscribe via the World Wide Web, visit http://redfish.com/mailman/listinfo/friam_redfish.com or, via email, send a message with subject or body 'help' to friam-request at redfish.com You can reach the person managing the list at friam-owner at redfish.com When replying, please edit your Subject line so it is more specific than "Re: Contents of Friam digest..." Today's Topics: 1. the odd question (Phil Henshaw) (Nicholas Thompson) 2. The art of agent-based modeling (Jochen Fromm) 3. Re: The art of agent-based modeling (Marcus G. Daniels) 4. Re: The art of agent-based modeling (Jochen Fromm) 5. Re: The art of agent-based modeling (mgd at santafe.edu) 6. Re: The art of agent-based modeling (Michael Agar) ---------------------------------------------------------------------- Message: 1 Date: Sun, 13 Aug 2006 23:40:29 -0400 From: "Nicholas Thompson" <[hidden email]> Subject: [FRIAM] the odd question (Phil Henshaw) To: "Friam" <Friam at redfish.com> Message-ID: <380-22006811434029151 at earthlink.net> Content-Type: text/plain; charset="us-ascii" Phil, I hate it when one of my topics gets dropped, and therefore feel guilty for being one of the DROPPERS, here. Sometimes the discussions get so far reaching and technical that I am forced to "pass over them in silence" as Wittegenstein said. the only piece of your message that I have anything nearly competent to say about is your .... "when modern science took an interest in complex systems it, concentrated on theory rather than on carefully documenting the physical phenomenon." I wonder if this isnt a common occcurence in science. Think of Evolutionary Biology Darwinism has a much stronger hand on its theories than it does on the things those theories explain. Think for a moment about our realtive grasp on "natural selection" and "adaptation". Natural selection is supposed to the be "cause" of adaptation, yet we seem to understand the cause much better than we understand the effect. Ask an evolutionary biologist to define adaptation: 90 percent will use the word natural selection in their definitions, because they dont have clue what they mean by adaptation. Thus, it doesnt surprise me that wise and sophisticated people can talk about the theory of complexity without having a clue what they mean by it. I got a group of people to gether at Clark a few years back to start a research project on emergence in human social groups. We were NEVER able to come up with a phenomenon that everybody agreed was an instance of emergence. -------------- next part -------------- An HTML attachment was scrubbed... URL: /pipermail/friam_redfish.com/attachments/20060813/be24b22f/attachment-00 01.h tml ------------------------------ Message: 2 Date: Mon, 14 Aug 2006 14:14:55 +0200 From: "Jochen Fromm" <[hidden email]> Subject: [FRIAM] The art of agent-based modeling To: "'The Friday Morning Applied Complexity Coffee Group'" <friam at redfish.com> Message-ID: <000701c6bf9b$41129210$976fa8c0 at Toshiba> Content-Type: text/plain; charset="US-ASCII" One question I meet again and again if I try to make meaningful agent-based simulations is: - How do we simulate the core of a problem without merely constructing an illustration of our own beliefs and assumptions ? In other words: How detailed should an agent-based simulation be ? If the goal is "to capture the principal laws behind the exciting variety of new phenomena that become apparent when the many units of a complex system interact", as Tamas Vicsek says in http://angel.eltehu/~vicsek/images/complex.pdf <http://angel.elte.hu/~vicsek/images/complex.pdf> then how do we design models that are complex enough but not too complex ? -If the simulation is too simple and matches your own theoretical ideas, then no matter how good these ideas are it is always easy to criticize that the simulation is either not realistic enough or only constructed to illustrate your own ideas and assumptions. -If the simulation is too complex and matches official experimental data, everything takes a lot amount of time (creation, setup and execution of the experiment and finally the cumbersome analysis of the complex outcomes), and it becomes increasingly difficult to identify the principal laws, because it is easy to get lost in the data or bogged down in details The "art of agent-based modeling" looks really like an art to me, something only mastered by a few scientists (for instance Axelrod). Grimm et al. propose 'pattern-oriented modeling', Macy and Willer say "Keep it simple" and "Test validity". What do you think is the best solution for this problem ? Macy and Willer "From Factors to Actors: Computational Sociology and Agent-Based Modeling" http://www.casos.cs.cmu.edu/education/phd/classpapers/Macy_Factors_2001. Grimm et al. "Pattern-oriented modeling of agent-based complex systems" Science Vol. 310. no. 5750 (2005) 987-991 http://www.ufz.de/index.php?de=4976 -J. -----Original Message----- From: Michael Agar Sent: Saturday, August 12, 2006 5:05 PM To: The Friday Morning Applied Complexity Coffee Group Subject: [FRIAM] complexity and society [...] If you are considering a model, I like Axelrod's way of thinking about them. He sees them as "thought experiment labs" for a conclusion based on social research. So first of all the social research has to be solid to really do it properly. More often than not it isn't. The lab let's you test arguments of the form, if people do things in particular ways properties will emerge at the level of society. By "test" I mean it lets you see if the conclusion can be "generated," to use Epstein and Axtell's concept, in just the way your social research suggests that it can. It's a way of making the argument that underlies the conclusion explicit so it can be better evaluated, and it allows for exploration of the space of results that the same argument produces and alternative spaces given control parameter changes. It's a test of plausibility and an exercise in clarity, nothing more, nothing less. [...] ------------------------------ Message: 3 Date: Mon, 14 Aug 2006 08:07:05 -0600 From: "Marcus G. Daniels" <[hidden email]> Subject: Re: [FRIAM] The art of agent-based modeling To: The Friday Morning Applied Complexity Coffee Group <friam at redfish.com> Message-ID: <44E08389.5070109 at santafe.edu> Content-Type: text/plain; charset=ISO-8859-1; format=flowed Jochen, -If the simulation is too complex and matches official experimental data, everything takes a lot amount of time (creation, setup and execution of the experiment and finally the cumbersome analysis of the complex outcomes), and it becomes increasingly difficult to identify the principal laws, because it is easy to get lost in the data or bogged down in details This may be a false choice. In the case of having some data of moderate resolution, there's no point in making a hugely elaborate model and simulation, because you'll never be able to validate beyond your data anyway. And if you don't validate, although the modeling still may be useful as an thought experiment, it isn't science. You have to be able to say something that can be shown to be wrong. If you do aim to learn things about the world and then predict them it's not desirable to have giant black box with lots of moving parts. It's better, if at all possible, to have a simple story and make the simulation nothing more than apparatus to help extend the data so that the dynamics can be studied by theoreticians. Another mode of use for ABMs is to lower expectations of theoretical traction and opportunistically look for ways a model makes useful predictions and then modify the model in that direction over time. This is a risky and expensive craft, but one that might have high enough payoffs to consider (e.g. national security). It depends on the data and what is of interest. If the data tells you about a number of rare events, and it is these events is what you really care about, then it may make sense to loosely model everyday behaviors and focus on model microstructure that can create the rare events you care about. Finally, sometimes microstructure is known with clearly defined degrees of freedom, and the dynamics are of interest. Consider modeling a factory where different assembly regimes are to be evaluated.. There's no need to validate here because the whole exercise is to answer what-ifs about realizable specific systems. Marcus ------------------------------ Message: 4 Date: Mon, 14 Aug 2006 17:04:40 +0200 From: "Jochen Fromm" <[hidden email]> Subject: Re: [FRIAM] The art of agent-based modeling To: "'The Friday Morning Applied Complexity Coffee Group'" <friam at redfish.com> Message-ID: <000801c6bfb2$f76ede80$976fa8c0 at Toshiba> Content-Type: text/plain; charset="US-ASCII" Of course it is the essence of science to verify hypotheses by experiments. Yet sometimes we have neither suitable experimental data nor a solid theory, for example in the case of very large agent-based systems (for instance for the self-organization and self-management of large internet applications on planetary scale, or the modeling of historical processes with millions of actors). It is hardly possible to examine these systems without simplified models, and in this case the questions I mentioned seem to be justified. In traditional "factor-based" or "equation-based modeling" we use differential equations and everything is based on a soild theory: mathematics. This traditional modeling has a century-long history and we know the suitable parameters, equations and models. Agent-based modeling has a short history, we don't know exactly the suitable parameters, agents and models, and worst of all it is not based on a solid theoretical theorem-lemma-proof science or calculus like mathematics. What is missing is a solid science of ABM or a new science of complexity - something in the direction of Wolfram's NKS idea (exploring computational universes in a systematic way). Just as formal, symmetrical and regular systems can be described by mathematics and 'equation-based modeling', complex systems can in principle be described by a 'NKS' and agent-based modeling - which seems to be more an art than a science. -J. ------------------------------ Message: 5 Date: Mon, 14 Aug 2006 09:50:59 -0600 From: [hidden email] Subject: Re: [FRIAM] The art of agent-based modeling To: The Friday Morning Applied Complexity Coffee Group <friam at redfish.com> Message-ID: <1155570659.44e09be35f52a at webmail.santafe.edu> Content-Type: text/plain; charset=ISO-8859-1 Quoting Jochen Fromm <fromm at vs.uni-kassel.de>: Just as formal, symmetrical and regular systems can be described by mathematics and 'equation-based modeling', complex systems can in principle be described by a 'NKS' and agent-based modeling - which seems to be more an art than a science. In context, I think is a verification issue. ABMs are useful for poking around a complicated system to see what matters and what doesn't by using a familiar and direct way of describing things, and to leave the abstractions for later. ABMs complement traditional techniques of analysis by extending data. The imperative programming languages that are typically used to make the simulations are prone to a variety of programming mistakes but the continue to be used because 1) they are common and 2) they provide an easy way to think about side effects (e.g. modifications to a landscape). Equation-based modelling is more like functional programming, e.g. programming languages like Haskell that are side-effect free. I see ABMs moving to these kinds of programming languages so that components of a simulation can be shown to be correct, and preferably by automated means. As a practical matter, I think it isn't a big deal. Unit testing during development by experienced programmers/modelers does a good job of shaking out bugs. Marcus ------------------------------ Message: 6 Date: Mon, 14 Aug 2006 09:58:05 -0600 From: Michael Agar <[hidden email]> Subject: Re: [FRIAM] The art of agent-based modeling To: The Friday Morning Applied Complexity Coffee Group <friam at redfish.com> Message-ID: <18528635-4305-4EB8-8D01-CA9C885E3826 at anth.umd.edu> Content-Type: text/plain; charset=US-ASCII; delsp=yes; format=flowed On Aug 14, 2006, at 6:14 AM, Jochen Fromm wrote: - How do we simulate the core of a problem without merely constructing an illustration of our own beliefs and assumptions ? I'd change this to How do we make clear the core of a problem through constructing an illustration of our own beliefs and assumptions and say that's exactly what both great science and great art do. Science then has the obligation to challenge it against new instances of the problem in the classic Popperian way. Mike ------------------------------ _______________________________________________ Friam mailing list Friam at redfish.com http://redfish.com/mailman/listinfo/friam_redfish.com End of Friam Digest, Vol 38, Issue 29 ************************************* -------------- next part -------------- An HTML attachment was scrubbed... URL: /pipermail/friam_redfish.com/attachments/20060814/1c2705bb/attachment-0001.html |
Free forum by Nabble | Edit this page |